privatization – P2P Foundation https://blog.p2pfoundation.net Researching, documenting and promoting peer to peer practices Sat, 15 May 2021 16:30:34 +0000 en-US hourly 1 https://wordpress.org/?v=5.5.15 62076519 Lagos, Nigeria: The Our Water, Our Rights Campaign https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/lagos-nigeria-the-our-water-our-rights-campaign/2018/07/04 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/lagos-nigeria-the-our-water-our-rights-campaign/2018/07/04#respond Wed, 04 Jul 2018 07:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=71595 Since 2014, the Our Water Our Rights Campaign has mobilized communities and people’s groups to resist water privatization across Lagos, and broadened citizen engagement in resolving the city’s water crisis. Against the odds it has also increased government spending on water and sanitation in the capital. When ERA learned that Lagos state government was secretly... Continue reading

The post Lagos, Nigeria: The Our Water, Our Rights Campaign appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Since 2014, the Our Water Our Rights Campaign has mobilized communities and people’s groups to resist water privatization across Lagos, and broadened citizen engagement in resolving the city’s water crisis. Against the odds it has also increased government spending on water and sanitation in the capital.

When ERA learned that Lagos state government was secretly negotiating a public-private partnership for its water supply – in a city already severely underserved in terms of water services – it launched a campaign which to date has seen US$185 million in government funds allocated to ensuring clean water for Lagos’ people. These were funds that the government formerly argued were only available through public private partnerships.

One of the strongest examples of the campaign’s power is its challenge to the government’s plan to criminalize the use of informal sector water by people in need. ERA contested this rule at a public hearing, mobilized different communities and organisations to march through the streets. The government eliminated the clause.

While the government still has privatization plans (which ERA will keep contesting), the campaign has, for the first time since the end of the military regime, united many different organisations, social movements and communities in Lagos and spurred a national movement against water privatization.

The campaign has involved 30 organisations, including those representing civil liberties, health care, peace and development, and human, environmental, democratic, legal and labour rights.

Communities were the prime voice in this grassroots-driven campaign, which gathered testimonies of people’s experiences of water shortages and contaminated water. From the outset, ERA linked the struggle to other anti-privatisation struggles in the world. And, in collaboration with other international partners, prepared the Lagos Water Crisis: Alternative Roadmap for Water Sector, showing the government that the campaign offered real alternatives.

“This campaign has several remarkable aspects, including integration between a professional organization and affected communities, community voices being at the centre, co-working with international allies. The results and changes brought by the campaign are verifiable and concrete.”

– Sakoto Kishimoto


Transformative Cities’ Atlas of Utopias is being serialized on the P2P Foundation Blog. Go to TransformativeCities.org for updates.

The post Lagos, Nigeria: The Our Water, Our Rights Campaign appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/lagos-nigeria-the-our-water-our-rights-campaign/2018/07/04/feed 0 71595
Essay of the day: Transition towards a Food Commons Regime: Re-commoning Food to Crowd-feed the World https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/transition-towards-a-food-commons-regime-re-commoning-food-to-crowd-feed-the-world/2018/03/27 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/transition-towards-a-food-commons-regime-re-commoning-food-to-crowd-feed-the-world/2018/03/27#respond Tue, 27 Mar 2018 08:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=70197 Food as a purely private good prevents millions to get access to such a basic resource, since the purchasing power determines its access. With the dominant no money-no food rationality, hunger still prevails in a world of abundance. In this paper, the commons approach is applied to food, deconstructing food as a pure private good... Continue reading

The post Essay of the day: Transition towards a Food Commons Regime: Re-commoning Food to Crowd-feed the World appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Food as a purely private good prevents millions to get access to such a basic resource, since the purchasing power determines its access. With the dominant no money-no food rationality, hunger still prevails in a world of abundance. In this paper, the commons approach is applied to food, deconstructing food as a pure private good and reconstructing it as a commons that can be better produced and distributed by a tricentric governance system compounded by market rules, public regulations and collective actions. This narrative can sustain the urgently needed transition from the dominating agro-industrial food system towards a food system that is fairer to food producers, consumers and nature. Along those lines, food and nutrition security shall be understood as a Global Public Good and the price of food shall rightly reflect its value to society and its multiple dimensions, not just the value in exchange. Should food be consider as a commons, the implications for the governance of the global food system would be enormous, with examples ranging from placing food outside the framework agreements dealing with pure private goods, banning financial speculation on food or preparing international binding agreements to govern the production, distribution and access of food to every human being.

Transition towards a Food Commons Regime: Re-commoning Food to Crowd-feed the World (PDF Download Available).

Photo by albertstraub

The post Essay of the day: Transition towards a Food Commons Regime: Re-commoning Food to Crowd-feed the World appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/transition-towards-a-food-commons-regime-re-commoning-food-to-crowd-feed-the-world/2018/03/27/feed 0 70197
Now Underway, a Neocolonial Land Grab on Barbuda https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/now-underway-a-neocolonial-land-grab-on-barbuda/2018/03/21 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/now-underway-a-neocolonial-land-grab-on-barbuda/2018/03/21#comments Wed, 21 Mar 2018 08:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=70157 Since 1834, when slavery was abolished on the Caribbean island of Barbuda, land there has been owned as a commons. The entire population collectively owns and controls the land, not private owners and developers. That may be about to change – with all the catastrophic results usually associated with enclosure. After Hurricane Irma devastated 90%... Continue reading

The post Now Underway, a Neocolonial Land Grab on Barbuda appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Since 1834, when slavery was abolished on the Caribbean island of Barbuda, land there has been owned as a commons. The entire population collectively owns and controls the land, not private owners and developers. That may be about to change – with all the catastrophic results usually associated with enclosure.

After Hurricane Irma devastated 90% of the island’s buildings last year, it forced virtually all 1,800 residents to relocate to nearby Antigua or cities like New York and Toronto.  International investors, working with Prime Minister Gastone Brown, a former banker, decided it was a ripe time to invoke the Shock Doctrine. This is the idea popularized by journalist Naomi Klein to describe how the market/state collusion to exploit national crises to ram through predatory neoliberal policies, which would otherwise be fiercely resisted by the citizenry.

In a great piece of reportage in The Intercept (January 23, 2018), Naomi Klein and Alleen Brown describe how the island government is taking advantage of the diaspora of Bardua residents. With no one around, it is an opportune moment to try to privatize the land and eliminate the communal ownership that has existed in Barbuda for nearly 200 years. A senator on the island described the communal ownership as something that was “born in the bowels of slavery and continued to grow in the post-emancipation world.”

The ostensible goal of the privatization policy is to provide a humanitarian response to the hurricane by facilitating outside investment and development. But the real goal is to open the door to investors and developers, who have long resented the democratic limits on development on Barbuda. They are eager to buy up pristine Caribbean land at bargain-basement prices and spur standard-issue Caribbean luxury resorts and ancillary businesses. The most notable such investor is actor Robert De Niro, who plans to build a luxury complex called Paradise Found Nobu.

According to Klein and Brown, “a sweeping 13-page ‘amendment‘ to the hard-won Barbuda Land Act was officially introduced in Antigua and Barbuda’s House of Representatives” on December 12, 2017.  “It includes changes that entirely reverse the meaning of the law. In the amendment, a clause declaring Barbuda ‘owned in common by the people of Barbuda’ was deleted and replaced. ‘The fundamental purpose of the Act is to grant to Barbudans the right to purchase the [land],’ the amended act reads.”

An outrageous act of enclosure, cast in the name of humanitarianism. Not surprisingly, international media coverage of these developments has been virtually absent. One exception:  a twelve-minute video documentary by The New York Times.

The transition to a scheme of private ownership of land – and the rampant “development” that would ensue – would radically change the culture of the island and strip Barbudans of their control over their land and rights of self-determination. It would also force many residents to leave the island permanently because they could no longer afford to live there, except as employees at the new luxury hotels and resorts.

In light of the diaspora of residents, it is hard for the to fight back. If anyone knows of people or groups actively involved in efforts to save the communal ownership of Barbudan land, please let me know and I’ll share the information here.


Update: There is a Facebook group dedicated to the Barbuda land grab and recovery delays at www.facebook.com/barbudasilentnomore.

To my readers:  My apologies for the absence of blog posts in recent weeks.  I am in the middle of writing a book that I hope to complete soon. Thanks for your patience!

Photo by andryn2006

The post Now Underway, a Neocolonial Land Grab on Barbuda appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/now-underway-a-neocolonial-land-grab-on-barbuda/2018/03/21/feed 1 70157
The Case Against Bill Gates, Mark Zuckerberg and Philanthropy As We Know It https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/the-case-against-bill-gates-mark-zuckerberg-and-philanthropy-as-we-know-it/2017/06/19 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/the-case-against-bill-gates-mark-zuckerberg-and-philanthropy-as-we-know-it/2017/06/19#respond Mon, 19 Jun 2017 07:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=65991 Originally published on americanmagazine.org There was a time when I felt warmly toward the Frick Collection. I was a teenager when I first visited the mansion-turned-art-museum on New York’s Upper East Side. Around every corner was a painting that I had seen before in school or books—Hans Holbein the Younger’s 16th-century portraits of Thomas More... Continue reading

The post The Case Against Bill Gates, Mark Zuckerberg and Philanthropy As We Know It appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Originally published on americanmagazine.org

There was a time when I felt warmly toward the Frick Collection. I was a teenager when I first visited the mansion-turned-art-museum on New York’s Upper East Side. Around every corner was a painting that I had seen before in school or books—Hans Holbein the Younger’s 16th-century portraits of Thomas More and Thomas Cromwell, El Greco’s St. Jerome, the Vermeers. I did not know much about the paintings, or what they had to do with each other, except that they were all so important. And there they were, all together in this benefactor’s home, arranged (except for the gift shop and ticket desk) as if he still lived there. What a guy.

Last time I visited, I experienced the place quite differently. I had spent some of the intervening years reporting on social movements for a living, witnessing the violence and other forms of repression frequently wielded against those who take stands for their own dignity—as workers, as students, as migrants, as neighbors. I had learned that the history of my subject included Henry Clay Frick. During much his life, the public imagination associated his name not with famous art but with the breaking of the Homestead Steel Strike in Pennsylvania in 1892, a deadly operation that involved the use of Pinkerton mercenaries and the state militia. Mr. Frick spent most of his life organizing the production and sale of steel and other industrial products. Fine art was, in comparison, a hobby. Yet now, nearly a century after his death, certain masterworks can be viewed only by paying a visit to his home, frozen in time, where they are indefinitely imprisoned.

Frick-like behavior is such a familiar feature of cultural and economic practice in the United States that we rarely pause to question it. Mr. Frick was not alone. His contemporaries, like Andrew Carnegie, J. P. Morgan and Leland Stanford, had philanthropic hobbies of their own, in some cases to greater effect. Each found ways of wiping away spotty business reputations with unrelated beneficence, supplanting the public ambivalence or notoriety they had accumulated in life with enduring gratitude in death. Like feudal lords endowing monasteries, they bought themselves a measure of salvation in the afterlife—and we continue to let them do it.

We like to think that the selling of indulgences was an error of the past, yet the practice has passed into secular forms, and there are few Martin Luthers complaining of it.

We like to think that the selling of indulgences was an error of the past, yet the practice has passed into secular forms, and there are few Martin Luthers complaining of it. What goes by the name of philanthropy—literally, the love of people—and what the tax code regards as giving can rival the cynicism of the feudal indulgence business.

Microsoft Windows remains the world’s most widely used desktop computer operating system, but its chief salesman, Bill Gates, is now best known in relation to matters like health care, combatting disease in Africa and school reform. There is no question that Mr. Gates has proved his skill in turning buggy, insecure software into a global near-monopoly. Less clear is the meritocratic rationale for why this man’s foundation should rival the power of the World Health Organization, which is at least partly accountable to elected governments. One might also ask why a private-school-educated college dropout skilled at selling software holds singular influence over the future of the U.S. public school system—which his foundation consistently steers in the direction of Microsoft products. Yet long after anyone remembers the misfortune of running Windows Vista, Mr. Gates can expect enduring praise for pouring money into humanitarian pursuits. Just as I took Frick’s collection for granted as a teenager, we may even forget that there were choices to be made about public health and public education, and that Mr. Gates had an outsized role in making them. When most of us donate from our small excess, we express a concern and entrust the money to those with expertise; when Gates donates, he sets the agenda.

Now a new generation may out-Gates Mr. Gates. In December 2015, Mark Zuckerberg, the chief executive officer of Facebook, announced plans to transfer nearly all his Facebook stock to a vehicle for unrelated activities. He chose to do this through a limited liability company rather than a foundation, forgoing even the tax code’s spacious definition of philanthropy. The intended targets for this wealth, as for the Gates fortune, are health and public education, although, like the Gateses, they have limited direct experience in either field. (Mr. Zuckerberg’s wife, Priscilla Chan, at least, received a medical degree in 2012; neither she nor Zuckerberg attended public high schools.) Mr. Zuckerberg has demonstrated expertise in turning surveillance of people’s interpersonal activities into a profitable revenue stream through micro-targeted advertising. But there is as yet little reason he and his wife should be entrusted with the sway over our systems of health and public education that they are in the process of claiming. If we are to go on tolerating the self-canonization and attempted do-gooding of wealthy donors, we should expect them to actually be engaged in donating—not in the buying of indulgences, not in a vast privatization scheme to replace what could be public decision-making. This is advocacy; advocacy is fine, but we should call it what it is. If philanthropy means love of others, it must prove itself by entrusting the material of that love to the intended recipients. To believe in the dignity of other human beings is to honor their capacity to choose.

If philanthropy means love of others, it must prove itself by entrusting the material of that love to the intended recipients.

Philanthropy, that is, should be regarded as a subdomain of democracy, not an exception to it. We live in a time when economic stagnation and an authoritarian mood have put political democracy on the run around the world. Yet we also have more ways of hearing each other’s voices and making decisions together than ever before. Philanthropy could be a means for diverse, creative, collaborative acts of democracy—just what we need to regain the capacity to trust ourselves again, to remember the essential dignity that is our birthright. But only if it is real philanthropy. Giving should mean really giving, or giving back.

Natural Law and the Tax Code

The latest edition of the Catechism of the Catholic Church contains, among its many now-peculiar-sounding phrases, a doctrine called the “universal destination of goods.” Says the catechism: “In the beginning God entrusted the earth and its resources to the common stewardship of mankind to take care of them, master them by labor, and enjoy their fruits. The goods of creation are destined for the whole human race.” To the eye of God, as among the earliest Christians in Acts, all things are common to all people. Nothing is mine or yours, but it is ours because we are part of the same divine communism.

There is, of course, a very big but.

The catechism goes on, “However, the earth is divided up among men to assure the security of their lives, endangered by poverty and threatened by violence.” Our flawed and fallen nature makes God’s communism impracticable. Therefore “the appropriation of property is legitimate for guaranteeing the freedom and dignity of persons and for helping each of them to meet his basic needs and the needs of those in his charge.”

So, there is a pass for possessions. Property of some kind is needed and useful. It can even be good, since it can be a means of serving others. The ample theory and practice of Catholic capitalism, from the Medicis to Domino’s Pizza, depends on this exception to the underlying, communist rule. But then there’s another but; the exception goes only so far.

“The ownership of any property makes its holder a steward of Providence,” says the catechism. Property is not fully ours; it must be stewarded, and taken care of, and shared. “The universal destination of goods remains primordial,” the catechism insists. Thomas Aquinas put the matter this way in the Summa Theologica: “Man ought to possess external things, not as his own, but as common, so that, to wit, he is ready to communicate them to others in their need.” We hold property, yes, but we should hold it as if it is not completely ours. We should dispense with it that way, too.

The tax code has a way of confounding useful distinctions, including among kinds of giving. U.S. law may give us the impression, for instance, that any contribution to a 501(c)(3) or similarly tax-exempt organization equals a gift. But many such gifts are simply acts of either obligation, preference or reciprocity—like tithing at one’s church, or supporting organizations that promote one’s social opinions, or underwriting a public radio station to which one listens. That is a normal part of being a good community member, and it’s praiseworthy, but it is not really giving. It is more a matter of responsibility than philanthropy. Actual philanthropy, the love of people, the stewarding of Providence—these expect a fuller kind of gift.

Such gifts can come in different forms. They might be in the form of sacrifice—giving what it seems one cannot afford, expecting no worldly reward. They might alternatively be a matter of forfeiting excess—the wealth beyond one’s own needs, which the world’s imperfect property arrangements have delivered into one’s hands. In either case the gift, once given, is no longer one’s own. It never really was.

Pope Francis has made a point of challenging the common habit of mind in contemporary philanthropy that second-guesses the person in need, that presumes to know better. Will the food-stamp recipient spend it on junk food? Will that man on the street use your dollar for drugs or alcohol or a doomed lottery ticket? Francis denies us these questions, together with their presumptions. He reminded an interviewer just before Lent this year that, for the homeless man, maybe “a glass of wine is his only happiness in life!”

Democracy can be a tool, or a family of tools, for achieving the humility that wealth can otherwise lift beyond reach.

Giving to those who ask, said Francis, “is always right.” Before trying to instruct the asker, the giver should listen and learn. “In the shoes of the other,” the pope added, “we learn to have a great capacity for understanding, for getting to know difficult situations.”

Catholic Relief Services has adopted a framework known as “integral human development” to guide its work of giving around the world, drawing on statements from Pope Paul VI and St. John Paul II. It is an attempt to give in a way that presumes the dignity and autonomy of the recipient, that seeks conditions under which people can become more fully themselves through choices and relationships. It is also an attempt to back away from the presumption that a philanthropist is typically entitled to: the presumption of knowing what other people need better than the people in need do.

Another framework for dispatching such presumptions is democracy. Democracy can be a tool, or a family of tools, for achieving the humility that wealth can otherwise lift beyond reach. We tend to think of democracy as the purview of government, but it can also be a means of real giving. It can be a vehicle of Providence.

Participatory budgets

Mr. Zuckerberg, in a lengthy manifesto he published last February on “Building Global Community,” turned to a sort of democracy out of necessity. He admitted that Facebook’s employees, whether in Silicon Valley or satellite offices around the world, cannot fully predict the cultural sensitivities and local anxieties of its nearly two billion users. Combined with artificial intelligence, the platform would be relying on a kind of “community governance,” he wrote, and said that users should expect to see experiments in “how collective decision-making might work at scale.”

The kind of governance Mr. Zuckerberg describes strikes me more like disguised focus groups than a truly accountable democracy; the company’s structure would remain chiefly accountable to profit-seeking investors. But his nod to collective, digital decision-making is instructive. Democracy often gets blamed for the bureaucratic outgrowths of government, so we forget its efficiencies; spreading decision-making processes widely across a large and diverse society is, in principle, a far better way to meet people’s needs than trying to anticipate them through central planning. To the degree that markets work, this is why. But the trick is choosing the right processes for the right situations.

We are living through what could be a renaissance in techniques for doing democracy—and, potentially, for doing philanthropy.

Mr. Zuckerberg comes by his techno-utopianist enthusiasm for the challenge honestly. Alongside the present authoritarian revival in global politics, we are living through what could be a renaissance in techniques for doing democracy—and, potentially, for doing philanthropy. There has never been less reason for tolerating feudal, unaccountable pretenders to generosity.

Private markets have generated a proliferation of decision-making software—from tools designed for running a private company’s board elections to project management platforms for teams scattered around the world. Some tools require more tech-savvy users than others, and they rely on varied means of encryption and authentication. Old-fashioned elections can be organized more cheaply and securely than ever.

But some of the most important experiments enable new forms of participation altogether. Liquid democracy, for instance, is a system used by some of the new internet-based political parties spreading across Europe and South America. One of the leading implementations, DemocracyOS, comes from Argentina; there, the candidates for a political party agreed to vote however the users of the DemocracyOS platform directed them.

It is a system of cascading proxies, a blend between direct democracy and deference to expertise. Rather than electing a representative to make every decision on my behalf for a fixed period of time, under liquid democracy I can decide on every proposal for myself. But in most cases I will have neither the time nor knowledge to do so. I can therefore designate a proxy to vote on health-related matters, and another to vote on education. Maybe those proxies choose other proxies in turn. I can change my proxy at any time or opt to vote for myself. I choose my own level of involvement and step back responsibly.

Loomio, developed by a worker-owned cooperative in New Zealand, has become a popular platform for discussion and decision-making for online groups. An allied project, Cobudget, enables groups to pool donations and allocate them collaboratively. More examples are emerging from the “blockchain” technology that underlies the Bitcoin digital currency—enabling secure, transparent governance without need for a certifying authority. But not all of these democratic developments depend on boutique software; to reach people most in need, they must not. Participatory budgeting, for instance, is a technique developed in Porto Alegre, Brazil, that has spread to U.S. cities like Chicago and New York. There, largely through in-person meetings, neighborhood residents work together to determine how funds should be spent in their communities.

Democratic tactics such as these might be aids in a kind of philanthropy that gives more than it directs, that entrusts gifts more fully to recipients. But they are just tactics. What matters most is how they are deployed. I conclude with three possible strategies for a more democratic philanthropy.

Giving directly

Maybe the most obvious thing to do when wealth accumulates excessively should be to return it, recycling it to those from whom it came. The John Lewis Partnership, for instance, is a large retail chain in Britain. When one of the founder’s sons took over, starting in 1929, he began transferring ownership of the company into a trust, which would become owned jointly by its employees. This was not an outright gift; the employees gradually paid the family back. But the choice ensured that, from there on out, the company’s profits would go toward the many who produced them, not just the founding family or outside investors. It prevented further excess accumulation.

Mark Zuckerberg might consider doing something similar. Rather than transferring his Facebook stock into his own pet projects, he could put it in a trust owned and governed by Facebook users—say, through some of those “community governance” mechanisms he wrote about. Then users could benefit from and help to steward the valuable, personal data they post and share. Mr. Zuckerberg himself might find his own skills put to better use that way. Instead of seeking to transform fields in which he has little expertise, he could help guide the user community to being effective stewards of the company he did so much to build.

Instead of seeking to transform fields in which he has little expertise, Mr. Zuckerberg could help guide the user community to being effective stewards of the company he did so much to build.

A vast number of businesses face impending transition as their Baby Boomer owners depart without succession plans. Some are large factories, others are small stores and offices. It is a historic opportunity to share that wealth, through forms of cooperative ownership, with the very workers and customers who make those businesses work. This is a kind of philanthropy that honors the human beings in an enterprise, the people who might otherwise take a back seat to the imperative of profits.

Cooperative conversion, however, is not an option for many who are in a position to give. A second kind of philanthropy more closely resembles the forms we are used to: delivering a set of resources to a community or cause.

When donors discern the need to direct funds toward some particular purpose, they can at least step aside after the gift has been made. Conventionally, philanthropic foundations remain, after the original donor’s death, under the control of family members or the donor’s stringent directives. Givers seem unable to allow themselves to fully give. We should expect better; even when the donor frames an original purpose, a more appropriate set of stakeholders can steer the gift afterward.

For instance, if a donor wants to set up a foundation for education in a given city, it could ensure that a significant portion of the decision-making process includes ordinary students and parents there. Rather than imposing elections, the foundation could assign rotating oversight positions through random sortition, just as juries are chosen. Or it could hold open meetings for a participatory budgeting process. If the recipients of the gift are more widespread, such as patients with a rare disease, online tools like liquid democracy or Cobudget may be more appropriate. One way or another, in order for a gift to be regarded as truly a gift, it should be given in a way that is accountable to its recipients, rather than as an imposition on them.

In order for a gift to be regarded as truly a gift, it should be given in a way that is accountable to its recipients, rather than as an imposition on them.

A third strategy for democratic philanthropy relinquishes donor control even further, and it is already starting to become popular: direct cash transfers. Just give people money and trust them to decide how best to use it.

GiveDirectly, a Silicon Valley darling, is a charity that uses mobile payment technology to deliver money into the accounts of poor people in Kenya and Uganda. The Taiwanese Buddhist charity Tzu Chi has also made lower-tech cash transfers integral to its disaster relief programs. This kind of giving includes no stipulation about how people use the money, but evidence appears to support positive outcomes; when people receive money with no strings attached, they tend to use it well. GiveDirectly has also become involved in research around universal basic income—a system by which every person (or adult) in a society would receive a livable income just for being alive. Advocates believe that, rather than disincentivizing work, a basic income would free people to make more valuable contributions to society than dead-end jobs by freeing time for education, family life and innovation. Some even contend that as more jobs become automated by technology, basic income could turn into a necessity.

Something like a basic income would require more resources than philanthropy is likely to provide (even though eight men now hold as much wealth as half the planetary population); full implementation needs public policy. But some philanthropists—including Facebook’s co-founder, Chris Hughes, now co-chair of the Economic Security Project—are putting the idea in motion by funding local experiments in cash distributions that could later lead to policy shifts. It is hard to imagine a way of giving more in tune with the universal destination of goods than this—recycling wealth among as many people as possible, with no stipulations whatsoever about how they use it.

These proposals, I realize, run the risk of inhibiting the philanthropic supply. If philanthropy cannot be a means of buying glory and immortality, one might ask, who would do it? Useful things have been done in the world by well-meaning but self-serving philanthropy. Are we ready to lose that by raising expectations?

Michael Edwards, a former Ford Foundation grantmaker, contends that the current system is not worth protecting. “Philanthropy is supposed to be private funding for the public good,” he has written, “but increasingly it’s become a playground for private interests.” However much the Zuckerbergs and the Gateses of the world succeed in their mighty ambitions, their chief achievement will be the cultivation of dependence on people like them.

“The more you try to control social change,” Mr. Edwards warns, “the less you succeed.”

Providence might do better.

Photo by J.Gabás Esteban

The post The Case Against Bill Gates, Mark Zuckerberg and Philanthropy As We Know It appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/the-case-against-bill-gates-mark-zuckerberg-and-philanthropy-as-we-know-it/2017/06/19/feed 0 65991
Working to Death: Leftist Critiques of Basic Income Fail to Offer Meaningful Alternatives https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/working-death-leftist-critiques-basic-income-fail-offer-meaningful-alternatives/2017/06/12 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/working-death-leftist-critiques-basic-income-fail-offer-meaningful-alternatives/2017/06/12#respond Mon, 12 Jun 2017 07:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=65927 Click here to read all our curated stories on Basic Income This post by Miles Krauter in collaboration with Carter Vance was originally published on Medium.com, here and here. From Finland to Kenya to Ontario, it seems that everyone interested in social policy is talking up basic income. It’s not a new idea, having been theorized since at... Continue reading

The post Working to Death: Leftist Critiques of Basic Income Fail to Offer Meaningful Alternatives appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Click here to read all our curated stories on Basic Income

This post by Miles Krauter in collaboration with Carter Vance was originally published on Medium.com, here and here.

From Finland to Kenya to Ontario, it seems that everyone interested in social policy is talking up basic income. It’s not a new idea, having been theorized since at least Thomas Paine’s musings on a “citizen’s dividend” in the late 1700s, and with variations actually having been piloted in several US cities and in Manitoba during the 1970s. Though many variations of the concept exist, with terms such as “negative income tax,” “basic income grant,” and “universal social payment” all signaling slightly different policy approaches, the basic idea is the same: the government would ensure, either by a direct payment or a top-up in the tax system, that all citizens (in some plans, certainly those proposed on the left, this would be extended to include refugees and permanent residents) not fall below a certain level of income per year. The exact level of cut-off varies between plans, but is usually located somewhere just above the Low-Income Cut-Off (LICO) in Canada, which is roughly $24,000 per year for a single adult, or a similar poverty measure in other jurisdictions. You wouldn’t have to work, or, indeed, do anything else other than breathe and sign up for the benefit in order to receive it. Sounds simple, right? The idea is quite tantalizing in its simplicity, being touted by its boosters as having the power to, at once, end absolute forms of poverty as well as provide social support to workers buffeted by automation and outsourcing, while giving more bargaining power to people trapped in the modern piecework of the so-called “gig economy.”

At the same time, for reasons that are understandable, there has recently been a set of voices on the left calling this idea out as too good to be true. To this side of the argument, basic income is being advanced as a Trojan Horse by governments attempting to maintain and deepen a neoliberal policy project while putting a new coat of paint on it to placate an increasingly restive public. They warn that a basic income will be used as cover for continuing cuts in health and educational services, along with privatization of other social programs, and state that leftists who advance even cautious cases for basic income are being played for suckers. While such arguments are not without merit in certain respects, they nevertheless fail to recognize both the traditions of social citizenship on the left that a basic income, at least in its leftist variation, speaks to, and the necessity for positive, emancipatory policy visions. Furthermore, these critiques also have the unwitting effect of continuing to unduly valourize “work” performed under capitalist conditions in a way that testifies to the deep penetration of certain harmful ideas about the sources of human dignity and worth into our collective social psyche. Basic income, properly formulated and applied with a critical eye, offers at least the potential of thinking about social organization in a different way. Given the upsurge of interest in the idea currently, those on the left would be foolish to not at least engage with it in order to shape the policy outcome.

The Dangers Are Real

Critics of basic income are right that BI programs should not be viewed as a panacea and that, absent a political struggle to make them the kind of basic income that is actually redistributive, they are not inherently a good thing. We can easily imagine a situation where a “basic income” program is instituted by a right-wing government in such a way that it is both inadequate to purchase basic needs and has its existence used as an excuse to slash other social expenditures (that are not adequately replaced by the BI) and to privatize public goods. To this end, there is a rightful caution to not simply take something called a “basic income” as doing what it says on the label, particularly when it is being advanced by governments with questionable records on social service. The “basic income” program currently being pushed by the right-wing government of Finland, for example, is nothing of the sort, and in reality has had more to do with an attempt to cut down expenditure on unemployment benefits. However, this is more of a basic point about not being bamboozled by flashy promises and to always be skeptical of the intentions of those in positions of political power than it is about basic income as a proposal in and of itself.

Any “basic income” proposal deserves intense scrutiny, as does any government policy proposal. In particular, aside from the actual levels of the benefits, we ought to be critical about who can receive the benefits (will it be conditional on citizenship?), the ease of receiving them (are we still going to have to make humiliating trips to the social services office?), and what other benefit programs are going to be phased out as a result. This level of scrutiny, in fact, could actually temper some of the left criticisms of left BI, such as the argument that any adequate BI would be so expensive, that left proponents of it are simply dreaming.

Any evaluation of the costs of a left BI must account for the fact that it would need to be gradually implemented (just like hikes to the minimum wage), and that it could eventually adequately replace welfare, disability benefits and tax credits rendered redundant. It must also account for the money that would be saved on less-burdened healthcare and justice systems, as well as the multiplier effects attendant to cash transfers to people with little capital. Finally, left critics of BI should understand that left proponents are generally banking on significant changes to our national revenue streams to sustain a generous BI, such as quantitative easing for the people, increased taxes on the wealthy (financial transaction, corporate, income, luxury, inheritance, etc), but also increased public ownership; is it too fantastical to dream of new automation-exploiting crown corporations directly funding a BI scheme? The left critic response is, presumably, yes, because none of this is ‘on offer.’ Like so many ‘realist’ arguments, this one’s cynical assumptions have a more narrow view of reality — potential and current — than what is warranted.

One of the assumptions underpinning this line of criticism appears to be that a genuinely democratic socialist government, or at least one capable of pushing politics in that direction, is out of reach. This is presumably so, under this line of argument, because change necessarily comes from below, and worker power is not at a point where a transformational government is feasible or sustainable. This view of political change assumes the forces behind (socialist) change to be unidirectional and linear, necessarily building from below and emanating upwards. Of course, this is truer than the reverse assertion, but the reality is more dialectical: forces at the macro scale can also feed into and grow forces for change from below. This has been demonstrated most recently by the campaigns of Jeremy Corbyn and Bernie Sanders. History consistently demonstrates that socialist-inspired programs and policies generally appear to be out of reach — until they aren’t. Advocacy of BI within a broader left policy framework is coming to the fore in France (the programs of both Benoit Hamon and Jean-Luc Melenchon advocated versions of a BI), in the UK (with John McDonnell promising to win the BI argument in the UK’s Labour Party), and even the federal NDP in Canada appears to be moving in a leftward direction generally, with space for a BI as a plank in that broader program. Meanwhile, it seems highly unlikely that the — presumably outgoing — Ontario Liberals will ever convert their problematic pilot project BI into implemented provincial policy.

Further, the idea that BI is merely some kind of bait-and-switch is belied by the fact that previous BI experiments have yielded positive social results. In the Manitoba “Mincome” case, crime, hospitalizations, mental health-related incidents and general social stress all declined, while wages at entry level jobs rose at a level above the provincial average. Though that and other pilots were unfortunately terminated too early to fully analyze their effects, the evidence we do have suggests that such a program would be likely to increase bargaining power at work, rather than decrease it. It is perhaps true that some boosters for BI have oversold it by presenting the idea as a panacea to a wide variety of social ills, but that observation should not lead to the overcorrection of outright dismissal.

A further critique within this vein links basic income to its sometimes supporters amongst the likes of Silicon Valley CEOs, with the idea that the program will merely be a form of noblesse oblige whereby such crumbs stave off absolute destitution amongst the masses, while income inequality grows ever higher. Again, this is not entirely without merit, and it is certainly possible to see how such a scenario would come to pass. But, in saying that this in itself should make BI a dead letter for the left, a couple of basic historical and tactical points are ignored. For instance, even though Bismarck created the foundations of the modern European welfare state as an explicit way of heading off the rise of socialist politics, this does not mean the welfare state itself is inherently a poison chalice. Though sometimes making critiques of its paternalism, its lack of inclusivity and its need to be more democratically organized, defense of the welfare state is one of the causes most near-and-dear to the modern left, including those who critique basic income.

Guilt-by-association will not do in this case, particularly given that it could be just as easily argued that we sully ourselves by association with public healthcare and old age pensions since these programs are currently supported by so-called “welfare nationalist” groups and parties of the right, as well as being historically implemented by a wide variety of political forces for a wide variety of reasons. Indeed, Canadian public healthcare was, in part, achieved thanks to the Conservative Diefenbaker government, which helped T.C. Douglas fund the Saskatchewan Plan, and the later Liberal government who oversaw the introduction of the federal Medicare program. All of this, of course, took place in a context of social and labour mobilization and agitation in favour of such programs.

On a tactical level, dismissing BI off-hand even as there is a growing interest in it risks giving over the conversation entirely to the very neoliberal types that those doing the dismissing are ostensibly concerned about. Refusing to engage in a conversation is rarely a good way of shaping it, and the space for more radical action rarely comes in the absence of preceding reform. Even a modest implementation of basic income, which provided some benefits to a wide social strata, could be a good organization point for further reforms as it would create a more widely-held stake in cash-based assistance, which is currently deeply stigmatized and cordoned-off from the more popular parts of the welfare state. Like the introduction of other universal programs, BI would create a public that could then be mobilized to defend and enhance it.

It is sometimes said by left BI critics that the conditions for a livable basic income are impossible under capitalism, because capitalist states would not allow workers to have access to what amounts to a kind of permanent strike fund. But, again, this ignores a rather obvious point: that a welfare state of any kind should not exist if this were wholly true. Any kind of state-furnished provision, whether in-kind or cash-based, allows workers to exercise some degree more leverage when negotiating with employers (otherwise, would Republicans constantly be trying to remove food stamp eligibility for workers on strike?). To this extent, we already have some degree of “strike funds” within the current makeup of the welfare state.

Basic income can be won on the same terms, which is to say via political struggle, that those other forms of social provision were, and though it may seem impossible at the current moment to see a future with a sufficiently high BI program, it is doubtless true that public healthcare once seemed such an impossible dream as well. Even as it stands, ‘public healthcare’ in Canada, and in many other countries, remains insufficient — an unfinished project. Yet, this universal program, even in its flawed state, is doubtless worth supporting. The analogy to public healthcare is helpful, as it highlights the importance of universal programs vis-a-vis workplace contingent benefits. Certainly, the American model of healthcare, which remains very much contingent on one’s workplace, is not ideal, and would not be ideal even if the state set a floor for health benefits at each workplace. BI, then, could potentially be seen as a kind of nationalization or decommodification of the wage, on the path to increased separation of means of subsistence from capitalists and the workplace. That said, we should not expect the most ideal BI to be the one that is implemented at first, but we can struggle for BI to be enhanced and expanded once implemented.

Work Sucks! Let’s Do Less of It (but Still Get Paid)!

At a more basic level, though, the left case against basic income is fundamentally uninspiring, on both the strategic and the philosophical levels. On the first, it is curious that critics tend not to offer their own prescription for tackling some of the core concerns that BI speaks to. Yes, they will sometimes gesture in the direction of either a full-employment policy (which may be problematic in and of itself on environmental grounds, and is vulnerable to some of the same critiques of BI concerning what state and capitalism can and will permit), or some combination of increased welfare rates and expanded in-kind social service provision, but in most cases they prefer to keep the conversation on increasing wages, expanding collective bargaining and updating labour law protections, particularly for precarious workers. This is not to say that all of these shouldn’t be on the menu of left goals, in particular turning those sectors of the economy which are growing (such as home health care and customer service) into relatively desirable, secure positions. Even with a robust basic income in place, there would still be a need for increased investment in in-kind services such as health care and education and the left should be committed to fighting for those. However, we should also recognize that these programs are not necessarily a response in themselves to the questions that left advocates of basic income are putting forward. It is not exactly clear how the prescription often offered by these critics of higher social assistance rates combined with a less restrictive and punitive benefits system meaningfully differs from a system of direct cash transfers set a sufficiently high level. Further, administering this benefit through the tax system or some other state agency not heavily stigmatized and structurally problematic as the welfare bureaucracy would help to increase social buy-in to the idea of government cash transfers. Socialists usually argue in favour of universal, or at least widely distributed, welfare state interventions precisely for the reason that targeted services or benefits are more vulnerable to attack from the political right, so, it remains curious why they want to retain the structural essence of the social assistance system, even if they do want it to be more genuinely helpful in some general sense.

We are sensitive to the point that many individuals currently employed in the social assistance delivery system are genuinely attempting to help their clients and that they do, on many occasions, provide them with system navigation advice which goes beyond the monetary benefits they administer. We do not, unlike libertarian basic income advocates, see BI as a way to slash good-paying public sector jobs. However, those who oppose BI on grounds of these jobs being lost, particularly those in organized labour, should at least acknowledge that there are contradictions in the roles that workers perform within these environments, that their function has increasingly become to police the behaviour of individuals receiving social assistance, and that acting to protect these jobs without an actual stated plan to change their function appears parochial and impedes the development of solidarity between social strata. People receiving higher, less restricted, levels of monetary support would be less in need of “system navigation” assistance in the first place, and there is nothing to say that public employees currently charged with welfare case management could not be shifted to other, more genuinely helpful, functions in the event that a direct cash transfer came to replace social assistance as we currently know it.

Though it is right to be skeptical of the “automation” explanation for the loss of well-paid, unionized jobs in the manufacturing sector, it is nevertheless true that many rote tasks in factories and elsewhere no longer require nearly the amount of physical labour they once did. With machine learning and commercially-ready ‘AI,’ this effect is only likely to intensify over the coming decades. Doubtless, some new jobs will be generated to make up for those which are lost, but this points to a deeper question about what the purposes of “innovation” and, indeed, work itself are. If the left response to the proliferation of what David Graeber has described as “bullshit jobs” is simply to make them better remunerated, we would seem to simply be buying into the capitalist mindset that what society labels as “work” gives our lives meaning, regardless of how mundane and unfulfilling we find the tasks themselves. The tiresome folkloric tale of a coming ‘knowledge economy’ — told to us by neo-liberals and post-Marxists alike — amounts to little more than a euphemism for a service economy that is already here. Yet neither a job at Google nor a job at McDonalds, with their different approaches to enforced happiness, will lessen our reliance on alienated wage-slavery, even if the former is better paid and more pleasant than the latter.

Instead, why shouldn’t our program be focused on creating the maximum social benefit of technological change through political participation? In other words, in noting that technology has created vast wealth that is privatized, we nationalize it, either through a basic income, or a French-style reduction of working hours without reduction in pay, or any combination of policies in this direction. Recognizing that even those well-paid manufacturing jobs of yore were often unpleasant, alienating and intellectually numbing is not a hard thing to do (even Adam Smith wrote about it in Wealth of Nations), but when presented with at least the potential to overcome this aspect of life in post-industrial capitalist society, there is a demurring to the nostalgia of an older era. Instead of shifting the subject of social justice to a kind of social citizenship, which thinkers such as Eduard Bernstein and T.H. Marshall envisioned with the expansion of the welfare state, the thinking remains stuck on limited definitions of “work,” “worker,” and the “economy.”

The objection to this shift of emphasis, other than its fairly acknowledged political difficulty, seems to be that it betrays the classical Marxist notion of the “worker” as the central political identity and the workplace as the central point of political struggle within capitalist society. Moving away from this conception, therefore, threatens both the recognition of the capitalist economic base as the main determining factor of sociopolitical conditions and the notion of work as being key to the “species-being” of humanity. What this objection ignores, however, is that Marx was not using “work” to mean the now-general notion of remunerated employment, but rather an expenditure of productive effort. The alienation of this “work” occurs when one does not capture the full value of what one produces, but also when the work being done is not freely chosen or self-directed.

Under the utopian conception of a basic income future (in essence, automated machines do most or all of the unpleasant work and BI levels are set at a level at which no one needs to work for money if they do not wish to), people would still “work” in Marx’s sense (they would write, paint, create dank memes, etc), just not in the commonly understood sense. Marx even muses about something that sounds suspiciously like a BI proposal in his economic and philosophic manuscripts — “an equality of wages paid out by the communal capital” — as a ‘crude communist’ first step towards an end to alienated labour.

In all, such a notion of “work” appears to be deeply tied to an uncritical, productivist form of Marxist thinking which may have had relevance in another political context but appears hopelessly dated in the current reality. This is all to say nothing of the fact that there are many people who have disabilities which prevent them from “working” in the conventional sense of the term, either temporarily or permanently, who are entirely written out of this analysis and would likely stand to benefit most from a basic income. Even the removal of the often intrusive, deliberately demeaning and manipulative aspects of the current social assistance regime would be deeply beneficial here, absent higher benefit levels. Similar remarks could be made as to the way in which basic income would act to, at least in part, recognize unpaid care work, usually done by women, which is often not considered as “work” under the status quo.

A Legacy to Build On

Enhancing and expanding any less than ideal BI program will inevitably come up against the limits of state and capitalism, but it is unclear why this is a bad thing. Capitalism’s contradictions, and their attendant crises, are not going to be avoided through BI, or any other redistributive reforms for that matter. As socialists, we should hope to confront these contradictions when state supports are in place and the rungs of the societal ladder are closer together, for this is when those of us on the lower rungs are most healthy and most powerful, and least likely to be swindled by shock doctrine elites. Undoubtedly, one of the best ways to achieve redistribution is through workplace struggles, but we also need socialist governments to implement a framework that makes these more likely (and more likely to be successful). However, we must also recognize the need for socialist governments to implement other redistributive mechanisms that exist separately from the workplace, such as a BI, if we ever hope to achieve a post-work society, and not just a more equal capitalism.

Basic income-type plans have enjoyed purchase on the left for some time, with in particular such luminaries as Francis Fox Piven and Martin Luther King Jr. calling for their adoption in the late 1960s. More recently, books such as Nick Srnicek and Alex Williams’ Inventing the Future and Paul Mason’s Post-Capitalism have put the idea back on the table. At the same time, it is true that Austrian economic figures such as Fredrich Hayek and Monetarist’s like Milton Friedman also supported their own version of basic income, which involved the grant replacing most if not all of the existing in-kind welfare state provisions. It can often be unclear, in the current debate, from which direction particular proposals around “basic income” are coming from, and perhaps it is for this reason that so much confusion and discord around BI exists on the left.

However, there is a crucial difference between the two essential variations of the idea that bears repeating: the latter seeks, fundamentally, to liberate the market from the control of the state, while the former seeks to liberate human beings from the market. Accomplishing the dream of unalienated labour is no easy task, and it is doubtful that any one of us has the exact right cookshop recipe to make it so. That said, the leftist dismissal of basic income, though it emerges from genuine concerns as to the instrumentalization of BI, is at the very least premature. Moreover, it remains unclear why we should believe the public would be more likely to accept continued privatization and austerity with the presence of a BI (elites appear to be proceeding just fine without it). We struggle now for a higher minimum wage and against these forces; why would we not struggle for a higher annual income and against these forces in the future? The left should view BI, as it does most aspects of the welfare state, as a tool whose political character is dependent on a balance of social forces. Rather than dismissing the notion outright based on its also being supported by some neoliberal forces, we ought to be fighting to make it our own and to make the best version of it possible.

Carter Vance is an MA candidate in the Institute of Political Economy at Carleton University and a former legislative researcher with the offices of Erin Weir and Peter Julien. His writing has appeared online at JacobinTruth Out and Inquires Journal.

Miles Krauter is a PhD candidate in the Sociology Department, and an alumni of the Institute of Political Economy, at Carleton University. He is the Vice President External at his union, CUPE 4600, and an organizer with the Fight for $15 & Fairness Ottawa. His writing has appeared online at rabble.caRicochet, and Canadian Dimension.

Photo by familymwr

The post Working to Death: Leftist Critiques of Basic Income Fail to Offer Meaningful Alternatives appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/working-death-leftist-critiques-basic-income-fail-offer-meaningful-alternatives/2017/06/12/feed 0 65927
A Shareable Explainer: What are the Commons? https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/shareable-explainer-commons/2017/04/29 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/shareable-explainer-commons/2017/04/29#respond Sat, 29 Apr 2017 10:00:00 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=65068 New Economy and Social Innovation: Commons are often associated with natural resources like the oceans and forests — areas that belong to everyone. But commons are not just resources. They are not simply Wikipedia pages or the city grounds used for urban gardening. They comprise of a resource, a community, and a set of social... Continue reading

The post A Shareable Explainer: What are the Commons? appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
New Economy and Social Innovation: Commons are often associated with natural resources like the oceans and forests — areas that belong to everyone. But commons are not just resources. They are not simply Wikipedia pages or the city grounds used for urban gardening. They comprise of a resource, a community, and a set of social protocols. The three are an integrated, interdependent whole.

Outline

  • What are the commons?
  • Is there an example of a commons business model?
  • In what areas are commons active?
  • Is commons a new idea or are there examples from the past?
  • How do privatization and enclosure affect the commons?
  • What is the importance of digital commons?
  • What role can commons play in the actual economic and institutional crisis?
  • What are briefly the differences between commons and markets?
  • Further reading

What are the commons?

Commons should be understood as a dynamic, living social system — any resource that can be used by many could inspire people to organize as a commons. The key questions are whether a particular community is motivated to manage a resource as a commons, and if it can come up with the rules, norms, and sanctions to make the system work.

Is there a clear example of a commons-based business?

The internet provider Guifi.net in Catalonia shows how commons can create a new paradigm of organizing and producing. This bottom-up, citizen-driven project has created a free, open, and neutral telecommunications network based on a commons model. This is how it works: People put Wi-Fi nodes on their rooftops, which is extended and strengthened each time a new user adds a node to the network. Currently, Guifi.net’s broadband network has more than 30,000 active nodes and provides internet access to more than 50,000 people. The project started in 2004 when residents of a rural area weren’t able to get broadband internet access due to a lack of private operators. The network grew quickly over the whole region, while the Guifi.net Foundation developed governance rules that define the terms and conditions for all users of the network.


Installation of a “supernode” of Guifi.net’s network in the neighbourhood of Sant Pere i Sant Pau in Tarragona. Photo by Lluis tgn via Wikimedia Commons

The example shows that in creating any commons, it is critical that the community decides that it wants to engage in the social practices of managing a resource for everyone’s benefit. In this sense “there is no commons without commoning.” This underscores that commons is not only about shared resources — it is mostly about the social practices and values that we devise to manage them.

In what areas are commons active?

Examples of commons can be found today in different areas:

1. Local food sovereignty

2. City commons

3. Alternative currencies

4. Web-hosting infrastructure for commons

5. Creative Commons license

6. Open-source software

7. Open-source design/cosmo-local production

8. Academic research/open education resources

It is interesting to consider the improbable types of common-pool resources that can be governed as commons. Surfers in Hawaii, catching the big waves at Pipeline Beach have organized themselves in a collective to manage how people use a scarce resource: the massive waves. In this sense, they can be considered a commons: they have developed a shared understanding about the allocation of scarce use of rights.


Wolfpak of Oahu manages access to the biggest waves in the world. Photo via onthecommons.org

Is commons a new idea or are there examples from the past?

From a historical perspective, commons were an essential part of the economical and social system of rural societies before modernization took place. People in rural areas depended upon open access to the commons (forests, fields, meadows), using economic principles of reciprocity and redistribution. When common grounds were enclosed and privatized, many migrated to cities, becoming employees in factories and individual consumers, and lost the common identity and ability of self-governance. The modern liberal state separated production (companies) from governance (politics), while in the commons system these were an inseparable entity. In industrial capitalist societies, the market with its price mechanism became the new central organizing principle of society.

How do privatization and enclosure affect the commons?

Nowadays massive land grabs are going on in Africa, Asia, and Latin America. Investors and national governments are snapping up land that people have used for generations. All over the world, all aspects of life are being monetized with the expansion of private property rights: water, seeds, biodiversity, the human genome, public infrastructures, public spaces in cities, culture, and knowledge.

What is the importance of digital commons?

The internet has been an arena for experimentation and innovation, precisely because there is no legacy of conventional institutions to displace. Entire new modes of creative production have arisen on the internet that are neither market-based nor state-controlled. Open-source software, Wikipedia, and Creative Commons licenses have emerged as a new way of production that is nonproprietary and based on the collaboration of widely distributed, loosely connected individuals who cooperate with each other.

Prior to the rise of the web, commons were usually regarded as little more than a curiosity of medieval history or a backwater of social science research. Now that so many people have tasted freedom, innovation, and accountability of open networks and digital commons, there is no going back to the command-and-control business model of the 20th century. The full disruptive potential of this profound global cultural revolution is still ahead.

What role can commons play in the actual economic and institutional crises?

The commons offers a powerful way to re-conceptualize governments, economics, and global policies at a time when the existing order is incapable of reforming itself. The most urgent task is to expand the conversation about the commons and to ground it in actual practice. The more that people have personal, lived experiences with commoning of any sort, the greater the public understanding will be. In a quiet and evident way, the commons can disclose more and more spaces in our everyday life in which we can create, shape, and negotiate our lives.

What are the differences between commons and markets?

Commons: Rely on people’s altruism and cooperation
Markets: Believe humans are selfish individuals whose wants are unlimited

Commons: stewardship of resources
Markets: ownership of resources

Commons: individuals and collectives mutually reinforce each other
Markets: separation of individual and collectives

Commons: shared, long-term, non-market interests
Markets: individual consumers, short-term market relationships.

Further Reading:

  • Benkler, Yochai, The Penguin and the Leviathan: The Triumph of Cooperation Over Self-Interest (Crown Business, 2010).
  • Bollier, David, Think Like a Commoner: A Short Introduction to the Life of the Commons. (New Society Publishers, 2014)
  • Bollier, David, and Silke Helfrich, editors, The Wealth of the Commons: A World Beyond Market and State (Levellers Press, 2012).
  • Capra, Fritjof and Mattei, Ugo, The Ecology of Law: Toward a Legal System in Tune with Nature and Community (Berrett-Koehler Publishers, 2015).
  • Hardt, Michael, and Negri, Antonio, Commonwealth (Harvard University Press, 2011).
  • Sennett, Richard, Together: The Rituals, Pleasures and Politics of Cooperation (Yale University Press, 2012).

This piece, originally published on Shareable.net, was written by Bart Grugeon Plana, a journalist and contributor of the New Economy and Social Innovation Forum (NESI Forum). It is based on the book “Think Like a Commoner: A Short Introduction to the Life of the Commons,” by David Bollier.

Shareable is media partner of the NESI Forum, a nonprofit initiative that will bring together change-makers and thought leaders to conceptualize, discuss, and lay the foundations of a new economy, in Malaga, Spain, from April 19-22, 2017.

Photo by 4nitsirk

The post A Shareable Explainer: What are the Commons? appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/shareable-explainer-commons/2017/04/29/feed 0 65068
Podcast: Kevin Carson on Mutualizing the Water Commons https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/kevin-carson-mutualizing-water-commons/2016/06/04 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/kevin-carson-mutualizing-water-commons/2016/06/04#respond Sat, 04 Jun 2016 09:32:43 +0000 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=56681 Kevin Carson was recently interviewed by Andrew Stewart of the Rhode Island Media Cooperative on the issue of corporate water privatization, with an emphasis on commons-based ownership and cooperative management as an alternative. The original  interview podcast can be found here, along with a write-up by Stewart that hits on the highlights of the discussion.... Continue reading

The post Podcast: Kevin Carson on Mutualizing the Water Commons appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Kevin Carson was recently interviewed by Andrew Stewart of the Rhode Island Media Cooperative on the issue of corporate water privatization, with an emphasis on commons-based ownership and cooperative management as an alternative. The original  interview podcast can be found here, along with a write-up by Stewart that hits on the highlights of the discussion. Stewart’s essay is reproduced below, along with the podcast.

Andrew Stewart: Democratize when they privatize the water system

A recent story published by Dan McGowan about a report by the National Resources Network included the possibility of privatizing the water system in Providence for $372 million. Furthermore, a recent report by The Real News Network emphasized how disaster capitalists, to use a phrase coined in The Shock Doctrine by Naomi Klein, would utilize the heightened awareness about lead plumbing following the disaster in Flint, Michigan to gentrify historic black and brown neighborhoods through a mandatory plumbing replacement ordinance.

UdF-Mk9-
Carson

Kevin Carson of the Center for a Stateless Society has been analyzing and writing on these topics recently in these articles:

He has developed a novel concept in dealing with efforts to privatize the water supply that could hypothetically be enacted here in Rhode Island.

“I’m trying to advocate for things like mutualist ownership of former government property, ownership by the consumers or by the workers [by] transforming them into stakeholder cooperatives… Water resources strike me as something that’s ideal for ownership as a public commons and administration through stakeholder cooperatives,” says Carson.

With regards to the costs of renovations to the system including the necessary plumbing replacements, “[Renovations can be financed] by shifting funding to people who impose the most costs on the system that are currently protected from paying their fair share… If you look at Flint and Detroit, for example, and the kind of stuff that’s being done by Emergency Managers, generally the big commercial [and] big corporate water users pay much lower rates. Most of the water purification costs are imposed by industrial users but spread out over the rate payers at large and now that they’re cracking down on accounts in arrears, it’s almost entirely residential water users that are being shut off while there are commercial accounts that are hundreds of thousands or millions of dollars in arrears that haven’t been shut down because politically they’re the real owners of the system.”

Would such an operation be complicated for the municipality? “It seems like a fairly straightforward thing to me to transform the representation on the board of directors and the senior management, you just make the management of the local water system responsible to the rate payers with maybe worker representation as well instead of being appointed either by the municipality or by a private corporation… I don’t see any need to purchase to the extent that the water resources themselves are a natural commons already owned by the public rightfully and to the extent that the infrastructure has already been funded by the ratepayers, I consider it legitimately their own property already.”

And how could this cooperatizing be financed? “I’m a big advocate of mutual credit systems… I’m all for larger economic organization where it’s possible to do things like upgrade water systems without paying usurious rates of interest to get it done… Under the system we have now I just say ‘let’s see how much we can do in terms of shifting the payment of rates itself in the direction of fairness and how much that boosts the revenue and, if necessary, set the rates high enough to cover the renovation costs with the people that actually impose the costs on the system, the commercial and industrial users’.”

Click the player below to listen to my full interview with Carson!

Cooperatized utilities are not uncommon in this country. In the South, there are a good number of public utilities that were introduced to the region when the New Deal brought modern plumbing, telephone, and electricity to these states. Some that still exist today, according to Wikipedia, are:

  • Electric Cooperative Association
  • Rural Electric Association
  • Rural Electric Cooperative
  • Rural Electric Cooperative Corporation (RECC)- Mainly used in Kentucky
  • Electric Membership Cooperative (EMC)- Used in many states, such as Indiana, North Carolina, Georgia, Tennessee, Alabama, etc.
  • Rural Electric Membership Corporation (REMC)
  • Electric Power Association (EPA)- Mainly used in Mississippi
  • Power Cooperative
  • Energy Cooperative

Mutual savings banks are chartered by a central or regional government that has no capital stock and is owned by members that are subscribers to a common fund. Here are several such bank networks in Europe:

Screen Shot 2016-05-02 at 5.05.50 PM

The other alternative funding source of such efforts would be your neighborhood credit union. For example, Cranston Municipal Employees Credit Union is made up of that municipality’s workers as members and PGE Credit Union, located across from the central Post Office, serves federal and state government employees. Now if there were only some organized force in Rhode Island, currently engaged in a fight against gentrification, privatization, and other neoliberal austerity measures, that would encourage its worker-members to pool their monies in one financial institute.

It would be important here, after referring to Tom Sgouros’s book Checking the Banks, to create security mechanisms to prevent this from becoming a Ponzi scheme. The union would need to be legally prevented from getting involved in Wall Street-backed retirement and investment instruments that would grow fat cat wallets by hurting members. But cooperative banks have the capacity within their charters to be hindering such activities.

The website of the Rhode Island Secretary of State features two cooperative organization forms, one for consumers and one for producers, who in these contexts would be the utility workers. If churches, mosques, synagogues, and other civic organizations were to aid in a membership drive, it would be fairly easy to get all ratepayers onto the membership rolls rather quickly.

The post Podcast: Kevin Carson on Mutualizing the Water Commons appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/kevin-carson-mutualizing-water-commons/2016/06/04/feed 0 56681
Essay of the Day: the Near-Death Experience of Democratic Governance https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/essay-of-the-day-the-near-death-experience-of-democratic-governance/2016/02/17 https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/essay-of-the-day-the-near-death-experience-of-democratic-governance/2016/02/17#respond Wed, 17 Feb 2016 10:48:43 +0000 http://blog.p2pfoundation.net/?p=53845 Essay: Economics and the Near-Death Experience of Democratic Governance. June Sekera. GDAE Working Paper No. 15-02, May 2015. Excerpted from June Sekera: “Non-market public production makes up a quarter to a half or more of all economic activity in advanced democratic nation-states. Yet here in the United States the public economy’s ability to function productively... Continue reading

The post Essay of the Day: the Near-Death Experience of Democratic Governance appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
Essay: Economics and the Near-Death Experience of Democratic Governance. June Sekera. GDAE Working Paper No. 15-02, May 2015.

Excerpted from June Sekera:

“Non-market public production makes up a quarter to a half or more of all economic activity in advanced democratic nation-states. Yet here in the United States the public economy’s ability to
function productively on behalf of the citizenry is seriously imperiled.

In this paper I trace the connection between mainstream, market-centric economics and what James Galbraith has called “the collapse of the public governing capacity.” Marketization and its confederate, privatization, have led, sometimes intentionally, to the evisceration of governmental capacity, the downsizing of democracy and the dismantling of traditions of responsible public administration that are grounded in law and the Constitution.

Over the last decades, apostles of the market have intruded upon government a pseudo-market with outcomes ranging from the unfortunate to the disastrous. So-called “New Public Management” –“a child of neoclassical economics,” – has colonized and weakened every level of public administration.

Hollowed out through the cathartic of a “competition prescription,” the public sector time and again seems to fail us, so systems of performance measurement transplanted from profit-driven business models are being imposed across government, ostensibly to improve results and better supply what the populace wants and needs, but instead often leaving harm in their wake. We find our most basic public services and rights in jeopardy: from clean air and water to unencumbered judicial due process. While government “reinventors” boast about shrinking government, in reality a “submerged state” mushrooms through an explosion of private profitmaking contractors and behind the hidden hand of tax expenditures.

Yet, as I argue in this paper, there is no viable explanatory theory of the public non-market economy or of production within it, nor any consensus about how to measure public purpose or assess results in the public domain. Instead, a market-centric economics prevails in textbooks, university teaching and public policy, while private, market-mimicking motivations and values displace public purpose in measurement schemes.

We live in “a political economy that generates the conditions for its own failure.” Confined and constrained by the “doxic frame” of market superiority, “the state lacks basic conceptual tools to think differently.”

More than a century ago, the effective operation of the public economy was a significant, active concern of economics. But, with the rise of market-centrism and rational choice economics, government was devalued and allowed a role only in cases of “market failure.” The very idea of a valid, valuable public non-market almost disappeared from sight. So today we lack a coherent, comprehensive theory of the public economy.

We need to understand how public goods and services originate through collective choice and collective payment. We need to explain how the mechanisms of public production arise from and at the same time affirm the democratic process and constitutional governance. We need a theory of the public goods economy.

Toward that end, I outline the elements of a theory of the public non-market, and suggest a model to explain its forces, flows and dynamics. In the public non-market, it is not demand but identified societal need that is the driver, not exchange but “contingent flow” that is the overarching dynamic. Electorally-manifested collective choice is the generator of public goods and services, and collective payment is the financing source. With these inputs, democratically elected representatives legislate goods and services into being. Production takes place in a nonrival supply process wherein information sharing is the norm and invisibility a hallmark of effectiveness.

A cogent theory of the elements and dynamics of the public economy, and an acknowledgment of its complexity, can inform and improve public administration in theory and in practice and help rebuild the machinery of government. On the basis of such a theory we can also design appropriate instruments for measuring results and managing performance. As citizens of a democratic nation state we must recognize that public products originate with the polity, and that accountability is rather at the ballot box than the cash register.”

The post Essay of the Day: the Near-Death Experience of Democratic Governance appeared first on P2P Foundation.

]]>
https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/essay-of-the-day-the-near-death-experience-of-democratic-governance/2016/02/17/feed 0 53845